The State of Science Education: Subject Matter Without Context
Norman G. Lederman
Oregon State University
Introduction
The quality of pre-college and undergraduate levels of science education is currently being questioned. Although the reasons for concern about quality differ from nation to nation, the primary rallying point is the perceived level of scientific literacy among each nation's populace. Although the words may differ, the situation is not new. One can easily point to "critical" concerns voiced about science teaching and learning, and their associated reforms, for well over a century. In each case, whether the label "scientific literacy" was used or not, concerns have typically focused on the usefulness and relevancy of the subject matter included in K-12 science curriculum. More specifically, educators have historically been concerned with students' ability to apply their science knowledge to make informed decisions regarding personal and societal problems. The ability to use scientific knowledge to make informed personal and societal decisions is the essence of what contemporary science educators and reform documents define as scientifically literacy. Perhaps the most recent reform visions of note have been the National Science Education Standards and Project 2061 (AAAS) of the U.S. As was the case with most of their predecessors in the U.S. and elsewhere, these reform efforts stress the importance of conceptual understanding of the overarching ideas in science (e.g., cause and effect, equilibrium, structure and function, cycles, scale). Such ideas are believed to transcend the individual disciplines within science and are believed to be superior educational outcomes than the mere memorization of foundational discipline-based subject matter. The phrase "less is more" has often been invoked to communicate the desire that instructional time focus on in-depth understanding of a reduced set of unifying scientific concepts. Although the words are different, the message remains quite familiar.
There is an increased emphasis, however, in two areas that make the current reform visions significantly different from previous efforts: nature of science and scientific inquiry. Helping students develop adequate conceptions of the nature of science (NOS) and scientific inquiry has been a perennial objective in science education (American Association for the Advancement of Science [AAAS], 1990, 1993; Klopfer, 1969; National Research Council [NRC], 1996; National Science Teachers Association [NSTA], 1982). Indeed, this objective has been agreed upon by most scientists and science educators for the past 90 years (Central Association of Science and Mathematics Teachers, 1907; Kimball, 1967-68; Lederman, 1992). Presently, despite their varying pedagogical or curricular emphases, there is strong agreement among the major reform efforts in science education (AAAS, 1990, 1993; NRC, 1996) about the importance of enhancing students' conceptions of the NOS and scientific inquiry. In fact, "the longevity of this educational objective has been surpassed only by the longevity of students' inability to articulate the meaning of the phrase 'nature of science,' and to delineate the associated characteristics of science" (Lederman & Niess, 1997, p. 1) or scientific inquiry. Despite numerous attempts, including the major curricular reform efforts of the 1960s, to improve students' views of the scientific endeavor, students have consistently been shown to possess inadequate understandings of several aspects of the NOS and scientific inquiry (e.g., Aikenhead, 1973; Bady, 1979; Broadhurst, 1970; Lederman & O'Malley, 1990; Mackay, 1971; Mead & Metraux, 1957; Rubba & Andersen, 1978; Tamir & Zohar, 1991; Wilson, 1954). Consequently, it is only natural to ask whether there are reasons to believe that the recent reforms in science education are more likely to impact students' understandings than their predecessors. It is my view that the current reform documents' emphasis on the NOS and scientific inquiry are likely to have as little impact as earlier efforts.
Two critical and interrelated omissions that have typified previous efforts are, unfortunately, evident in the more recent reform documents. There is not, and there has not been, a concerted professional development effort to clearly communicate, first, what is meant by the "NOS" and scientific inquiry and second, how a functional understanding of these valued aspects of science can be communicated to K-12 students. Perhaps the lack of professional development related to the NOS and scientific inquiry is a consequence of the misunderstanding that the NOS and scientific inquiry fall within the realm of affect and process as opposed to cognitive outcomes of equal, if not greater, importance than "traditional" subject matter. The NOS and scientific inquiry are as much an aspect of subject matter as the reactions of photosynthesis or pH. In reality, however, it is the NOS and scientific inquiry that provide the context for the subject matter specified in the Standards and other reform documents. Furthermore, the NOS permeates all areas of the discipline-specific standards and it is a critical component of the standards on "science as inquiry." From the perspective of currently advocated pedagogy (i.e., constructivist approaches), an understanding of the NOS and scientific inquiry underlies the essence of the Teaching and Assessment Standards specified by the National Science Education Standards. It is not at all difficult to argue that a teacher who lacks adequate conceptions of the NOS and scientific inquiry, and a functional understanding of how to teach these valued aspects of science cannot orchestrate the types of instructional activities and atmosphere, or assess students' progress, as specified in the various reform efforts in science education. Indeed, a functional understanding of the NOS and scientific inquiry by teachers is clearly prerequisite to any hopes of achieving the vision of science teaching and learning specified in the various reform efforts. In the following sections, I will clarify the meaning of the NOS and scientific inquiry.
These terms are used with little precision and high variability within educational circles and it is necessary to insure that we are all on the same page regarding these important educational outcomes. I will also delineate several misconceptions promoted (or ignored) by reform efforts. It will further be argued that without explicit instructional attention to the NOS and scientific inquiry, students will once again learn science subject matter in a context-free environment. Such an environment does not permit the in-depth conceptual understanding of science subject matter advocated in the various visions of reform and will not help create a populace that can be considered scientifically literate.
What is the NOS?
The phrase "nature of science" typically refers to the epistemology of science, science as a way of knowing, or the values and beliefs inherent to the development of scientific knowledge (Lederman, 1992). Beyond these general characterizations, no consensus presently exists among philosophers of science, historians of science, scientists, and science educators on a specific definition for the NOS. This lack of consensus, however, should neither be disconcerting nor surprising given the multifaceted nature and complexity of the scientific endeavor. Conceptions of the NOS have changed throughout the development of science and systematic thinking about science and are reflected in the ways the scientific and science education communities have defined the phrase "nature of science" during the past 100 years (e.g., AAAS, 1990, 1993; California Department of Education, 1990; Center of Unified Science Education at Ohio State University, 1974; Central Association for Science and Mathematics Teachers, 1907; Klopfer & Watson, 1957; NSTA, 1982). It is my view, however, many of the disagreements about the definition or meaning of the NOS that continue to exist among philosophers, historians, and science educators are irrelevant to K-12 instruction. The issue of the existence of an objective reality as compared to phenomenal realities is a case in point. I argue that there is an acceptable level of generality regarding the NOS that is accessible to K-12 students and relevant to their daily lives. Moreover, at this level, little disagreement exists among philosophers, historians, and science educators. Among the characteristics of the scientific enterprise corresponding to this level of generality are that scientific knowledge is tentative (subject to change), empirically-based (based on and/or derived from observations of the natural world), subjective (theory-laden), necessarily involves human inference, imagination, and creativity (involves the invention of explanations), and is socially and culturally embedded. Two additional important aspects are the distinction between observations and inferences, and the functions of, and relationships between scientific theories and laws. What follows is a brief consideration of these characteristics of science and scientific knowledge.
First, students should be aware of the crucial distinction between observation and inference. Observations are descriptive statements about natural phenomena that are "directly" accessible to the senses (or extensions of the senses) and about which several observers can reach consensus with relative ease. For example, objects released above ground level tend to fall and hit the ground. By contrast, inferences are statements about phenomena that are not "directly" accessible to the senses. For example, objects tend to fall to the ground because of "gravity." The notion of gravity is inferential in the sense that it can only be accessed and/or measured through its manifestations or effects. Examples of such effects include the perturbations in predicted planetary orbits due to inter-planetary "attractions," and the bending of light coming from the stars as its rays pass through the sun's "gravitational" field.
Second, closely related to the distinction between observations and inferences is the distinction between scientific laws and theories. Individuals often hold a simplistic, hierarchical view of the relationship between theories and laws whereby theories become laws depending on the availability of supporting evidence. It follows from this notion that scientific laws have a higher status than scientific theories. Both notions, however, are inappropriate because, among other things, theories and laws are different kinds of knowledge and one can not develop or be transformed into the other. Laws are statements or descriptions of the relationships among observable phenomena. Boyle's law, which relates the pressure of a gas to its volume at a constant temperature, is a case in point. Theories, by contrast, are inferred explanations for observable phenomena. The kinetic molecular theory, which explains Boyle's law, is one example. Moreover, theories are as legitimate a product of science as laws. Scientists do not usually formulate theories in the hope that one day they will acquire the status of "law." Scientific theories, in their own right, serve important roles, such as guiding investigations and generating new research problems in addition to explaining relatively huge sets of seemingly unrelated observations in more than one field of investigation. For example, the kinetic molecular theory serves to explain phenomena that relate to changes in the physical states of matter, others that relate to the rates of chemical reactions, and still other phenomena that relate to heat and its transfer, to mention just a few.
Third, even though scientific knowledge is, at least partially, based on and/or derived from observations of the natural world (i.e., empirical), it nevertheless involves human imagination and creativity. Science, contrary to common belief, is not a totally lifeless, rational, and orderly activity. Science involves the invention of explanations and this requires a great deal of creativity by scientists. The "leap" from atomic spectral lines to Bohr's model of the atom with its elaborate orbits and energy levels is a case in point. This aspect of science, coupled with its inferential nature, entails that scientific concepts, such as atoms, black holes, and species, are functional theoretical models rather than faithful copies of reality.
Fourth, scientific knowledge is subjective or theory-laden. Scientists'theoretical commitments, beliefs, previous knowledge, training, experiences, and expectations actually influence their work. All these background factors form a mind-set that affects the problems scientists investigate and how they conduct their investigations, what they observe (and do not observe), and how they make sense of, or interpret their observations. It is this (sometimes collective) individuality or mind-set that accounts for the role of subjectivity in the production of scientific knowledge. It is noteworthy that, contrary to common belief, science never starts with neutral observations (Chalmers, 1982). Observations (and investigations) are always motivated and guided by, and acquire meaning in reference to questions or problems. These questions or problems, in turn, are derived from within certain theoretical perspectives.
Fifth, science as a human enterprise is practiced in the context of a larger culture and its practitioners (scientists) are the product of that culture. Science, it follows, affects and is affected by the various elements and intellectual spheres of the culture in which it is embedded. These elements include, but are not limited to, social fabric, power structures, politics, socioeconomic factors, philosophy, and religion. An example may help to illustrate how social and cultural factors impact scientific knowledge. Telling the story of the evolution of humans (Homo sapiens) over the course of the past seven million years is central to the biosocial sciences. Scientists have formulated several elaborate and differing story lines about this evolution. Until recently, the dominant story was centered about "the man-hunter" and his crucial role in the evolution of humans to the form we now know (Lovejoy, 1981). This scenario was consistent with the white-male culture that dominated scientific circles up to the 1960s and early 70s. As the feminist movement grew stronger and women were able to claim recognition in the various scientific disciplines, the story about hominid evolution started to change. One story that is more consistent with a feminist approach is centered about "the female-gatherer" and her central role in the evolution of humans (Hrdy, 1986). It is noteworthy that both story lines are consistent with the available evidence.
Sixth, it follows from the previous discussions that scientific knowledge is never absolute or certain. This knowledge, including "facts," theories, and laws, is tentative and subject to change. Scientific claims change as new evidence, made possible through advances in theory and technology, is brought to bear on existing theories or laws, or as old evidence is reinterpreted in the light of new theoretical advances or shifts in the directions of established research programs. It should be emphasized that tentativeness in science does not only arise from the fact that scientific knowledge is inferential, creative, and socially and culturally embedded. There are also compelling logical arguments that lend credence to the notion of tentativeness in science. Indeed, contrary to common belief, scientific hypotheses, theories, and laws can never be absolutely "proven." This holds irrespective of the amount of empirical evidence gathered in the support of one of these ideas or the other (Popper, 1963, 1988). For example, to be "proven," a certain scientific law should account for every single instance of the phenomenon it purports to describe at all times. It can logically be argued that one such future instance, of which we have no knowledge whatsoever, may behave in a manner contrary to what the law states. As such, the law can never acquire an absolutely "proven" status. This equally holds in the case of hypotheses and theories.
Finally, it is important to note that individuals often conflate the NOS with science processes (which is more consistent with scientific inquiry). Although these aspects of science overlap and interact in important ways, it is nonetheless important to distinguish the two. Scientific processes are activities related to collecting and analyzing data, and drawing conclusions (AAAS, 1990, 1993; NRC, 1996). For example, observing and inferring are scientific processes. On the other hand, the NOS refers to the epistemological underpinnings of the activities of science. As such, realizing that observations are necessarily theory-laden and are constrained by our perceptual apparatus belongs within the realm of the NOS.
Professional development efforts designed for teachers must not conclude, as they have in the past, with the development of adequate teacher understandings. The research is quite clear that teachers' understandings do not automatically translate into classroom practice. Certainly, teachers must have an in-depth understanding of what they are expected to teach. However, professional development efforts must also emphasize how teachers can successfully facilitate the development of students' understandings of the NOS.
What is Scientific Inquiry?
Although closely related to science processes, scientific inquiry extends beyond the mere development of process skills such as observing, inferring, classifying, predicting, measuring, questioning, interpreting and analyzing data. Scientific inquiry includes the traditional science processes, but also refers to the combining of these processes with scientific knowledge, scientific reasoning and critical thinking to develop scientific knowledge. From the perspective of the National Science Education Standards (NRC, 1996), students are expected to be able to develop scientific questions and then design and conduct investigations that will yield the data necessary for arriving at conclusions for the stated questions. The Benchmarks for Science Literacy (AAAS, 1993) are a bit less ambitious as they do not advocate that all students be able to design and conduct investigations in total. Rather, it is expected that all students at least be able to understand the rationale of an investigation and be able to critically analyze the claims made from the data collected. Scientific inquiry, in short, refers to the systematic approaches used by scientists in an effort to answer their questions of interest. Pre-college students, and the general public for that matter, believe in a distorted view of scientific inquiry that has resulted from schooling, the media, and the format of most scientific reports. This distorted view is called THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD. That is, a fixed set and sequence of steps that all scientists follow when attempting to answer scientific questions. A more critical description would characterize THE METHOD as an algorithm that students are expected to memorize, recite, and follow as a recipe for success. The visions of reform, however, are quick to point out that there is no single fixed set or sequence of steps that all scientific investigations follow. The contemporary view of scientific inquiry advocated is that the questions guide the approach and the approaches vary widely within and across scientific disciplines and fields.
At a general level, scientific inquiry can be seen to take several forms (i.e., descriptive, correlational, and experimental). Descriptive research is the form of research that often characterizes the beginning of a line of research. This is the type of research that derives the variables and factors important to a particular situation of interest. Whether descriptive research gives rise to correlational approaches depends upon the field and topic. For example, much of the research in anatomy and taxonomy are descriptive in nature and do not progress to experimental or correlational types of research. The purpose of research in these areas is very often simply to describe. On the other hand, there are numerous examples in the history of anatomical research that have lead to more than description. The initial research concerning the cardiovascular system by William Harvey was descriptive in nature. However, once the anatomy of blood vessels had been described, questions arouse concerning the circulation of blood through the vessels. Such questions lead to research that correlated anatomical structures with blood flow and experiments based on models of the cardiovascular system. To briefly distinguish correlational from experimental research, the former explicates relationships among variables identified in descriptive research and the latter involves a planned intervention and manipulation of variables related in correlational research in an attempt to derive causal relationships. In some cases, lines of research can been seen to progress from descriptive to correlational to experimental, while in other cases (e.g., descriptive astronomy) such a progression is not necessarily relevant relevant.
The perception that a single scientific method exists owes much to the status of classical experimental design. Experimental designs very often conform to what is presented as THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD and the examples of scientific investigations presented in science textbooks most often are experimental in nature. The problem, of course, is not that investigations consistent with "the scientific method" do not exist. The problem is that experimental research is not representative of scientific investigations as a whole. Consequently, a very narrow and distorted view of scientific inquiry is promoted in our K-12 students.
Scientific inquiry has always been ambiguous in its presentation within science education reforms. In particular, inquiry is perceived in three different ways. It can be viewed as a set of skills to be learned by students and combined in the performance of a scientific investigation. It can also be viewed as a cognitive outcome that students are to achieve. In particular, the current visions of reform are very clear (at least in written words) in distinguishing between the performance of inquiry (i.e., what students will be able to do) and what students know about inquiry (i.e., what students should know). For example, it is one thing to have students set up a control group for an experiment, while it is another to expect students to understand the logical necessity for a control within an experimental design. Unfortunately, the subtle difference in wording noted in the reforms (i.e., "know" versus "do") is often missed by everyone except the most careful reader. The third use of "inquiry" in reform documents relates strictly to pedagogy and further muddies the water. In particular, current wisdom advocates that students best learn science through an inquiry-oriented teaching approach. It is believed that students will best learn scientific concepts by doing science. In this sense, "scientific inquiry" is viewed as a teaching approach used to communicate scientific knowledge to students (or allow students to construct their own knowledge) as opposed to an educational outcome that students are expected to learn about and learn how to do. Indeed, it is the pedagogical sense of inquiry that it is unwittingly communicated to most teachers by science education reform documents, with the two former senses lost in the shuffle.
Communicating Functional Understandings of the NOS
The tone of my discussion implies that science education reforms, currently and in the past, have mishandled NOS and scientific inquiry. On the one hand, it has been assumed that teachers understand both of these important aspects of science and little professional development has been planned or provided. On the other hand, little has been provided to teachers regarding the teaching of scientific inquiry and NOS to students. The provision of professional development is closely linked to financial resources and the purveyors of reform can hardly be held accountable for what school districts, counties, states, and countries decide to provide. One could argue, however, that reform documents could present a much stronger case for the necessity of professional development.
However, there is a critical flaw in the various reforms' approach to the teaching of the nature of science and scientific inquiry. It is this critical flaw that has existed since the beginning of the science education community's recognition of the importance of scientific inquiry and the NOS as important educational outcomes.
Two general approaches have been advocated by reform documents and the science education literature to enhance students' and teachers' understandings of the NOS and/or scientific inquiry. The first approach, labeled here as an implicit approach, suggests that by "doing science" students will also come to understand the NOS and scientific inquiry (Lawson, 1982; Rowe, 1974). This approach was adopted by most of the curricula of the 1960s and 70s that emphasized hands-on, inquiry-based activities and/or process-skills instruction. Research studies have indicated that the implicit approach was not effective in enhancing students' and teachers' understandings of the NOS or scientific inquiry (e.g., Durkee, 1974; Haukoos & Penick, 1985; Riley, 1979; Spears & Zollman, 1977; Trent, 1965; Troxel, 1968). It should be noted that two interrelated assumptions underlie the implicit approach and compromise its effectiveness. The first depicts attaining an understanding of the NOS and/or scientific inquiry to be "affective" (as compared to a cognitive) learning outcomes. Indeed, it is not uncommon to find scientific inquiry often referred to as "scientific attitude." This first assumption entails the second assumption; the assumption that learning about the NOS and scientific inquiry will result as a by-product of "doing science."
The second approach, the historical approach (one that is strongly recommended by the National Science Education Standards), suggests that incorporating the history of science (HOS) in science teaching can serve to enhance students' views of the NOS. History of Science Cases for High Schools (Klopfer & Watson, 1957) and Harvard Project Physics (Rutherford, Holton, & Watson, 1970) were two notable curriculum development efforts that included substantial attention to the HOS at the high school level. However, a review of the efforts that aimed to assess the influence of incorporating the HOS in science teaching (Klopfer & Cooley, 1963; Solomon, Duveen, Scot, & McCarthy, 1992; Welch & Walberg, 1972; Yager & Wick, 1966) indicates that evidence concerning the effectiveness of the historical approach is, at best, inconclusive. And, most recently, the work of Abd-El-Khalick (1998) has indicated that specific courses in the history and/or philosophy of science have little impact on students' understanding of the NOS and scientific inquiry.
An alternative approach to the two often noted in the reforms suggests that the goal of improving students' views of the scientific endeavor "should be planned for instead of being anticipated as a side effect or secondary product" of varying approaches to science teaching (Akindehin, 1988, p. 73). This explicit approach uses instruction geared toward various aspects of the NOS or scientific inquiry and utilizes elements from the history and philosophy of science to improve learners' views of the NOS. In general, relative to the implicit and historical approaches, the explicit approach has been more effective in helping learners achieve enhanced understandings of the NOS and scientific inquiry (e.g., Akindehin, 1988; Billeh & Hasan, 1975; Carey & Stauss, 1968, 1970; Jones, 1969; Lavach, 1969; Ogunniyi, 1983; Olstad, 1969).
It is my opinion that a functional understanding of the NOS and/or scientific inquiry is best facilitated through an explicit reflective approach. I cannot overemphasize the importance of taking time, at the conclusion of any activity, to explicitly point out to students the aspects of the NOS and scientific inquiry that are highlighted. To encourage reflection, teachers must discuss with students the implications such aspects of the NOS and scientific inquiry have for the way they view scientists, scientific knowledge, and the practice of science.
In conclusion, it is important to emphasize that we should no longer assume that students will come to understand the NOS or scientific inquiry as a by-product of "doing" science-based or inquiry activities. Nor should we assume that if teachers understand the NOS and scientific inquiry, they will automatically teach in a manner "consistent" with those understandings. The NOS and scientific inquiry should be thought of as a "cognitive" rather than as an "affective" instructional outcomes. If K-12 students are expected to develop more adequate conceptions of the NOS and scientific inquiry, then, as any cognitive objective, this outcome should be planned for, explicitly taught, and assessed. All this can be facilitated through concerted and continued professional development efforts designed to promote science teachers' understanding of the NOS and scientific inquiry, provide approaches teachers can use to facilitate students' conceptions, and foster commitment to the idea that the NOS and scientific inquiry are instructional objectives of primary importance that permeate all aspects of curriculum and instruction.
Concluding Remarks
If you are at all like me, you may be wondering what the title of this paper has to do with what has been presented thus far. If you no longer remember the title, you may still be wondering what this all has to do with the state of science education and/or reform in science education. As you may recall, I began this discussion by distinguishing current reform efforts in science education from their predecessors with respect to the heightened interest and emphasis on scientific inquiry and the NOS. The primary reason for this heightened, but certainly not new, advocacy is the belief that students need to develop in-depth understandings of how scientific knowledge is generated and the implications this has for the status of the knowledge. Science educators have come to believe that if students understand the source and limits of scientific knowledge they will be better equipped to make informed decisions about personal and societal problems that are scientifically-based. In short, understandings of the NOS and scientific inquiry are believed to be critical and essential components of the modern day battle cry of "scientific literacy."
With respect to students' achieving in-depth understanding of subject matter, which is another component of the current reform efforts, it can be argued that such a goal is unachievable unless students understand the NOS and scientific inquiry. For example, can it be said that a student truly understands the concept of a gene if he/she does not realize that a "gene" is a construct invented to explain experimental results? Does the student who views genes as possessing physical existence analogous to pearls on a necklace possess an in-depth understanding of the concept? Does the student who is unaware that the atom (as pictured in books) is a scientific model used to explain the behavior of matter and that it has not been directly observed have an in-depth understanding of the atom?
Misconceptions about the scientific validity of biological evolution commonly appear in the media and courts of law. Many of these misconceptions relate to whether evolution is a testable scientific theory. The arguments against the validity of evolution usually proceed to point out that evolution can not be tested using the scientific method. Therefore, evolution can not be a valid scientific theory. Many feel that the problem is at least partially created by the public's misunderstanding of scientific inquiry and/or scientific theory. These few examples should make it clear that understanding the NOS and scientific inquiry provide a guiding framework and context for scientific knowledge. Without an understanding of how scientific knowledge is derived and the implications the process of derivation has for the status and limitations of the knowledge, all students can ever hope to achieve is knowledge without context. Context is necessary for students to understand what the knowledge means. In short, lack of context is the equivalent to playing a game of chess without knowing the rules of the game. Unless students can derive meaning for the scientific knowledge they acquire, there is little hope that they can use their knowledge to make informed decisions.
In many ways the state of science education and science education reform is exactly where it was 100 years ago. Today, just as we did at the turn of the century, we are seeking the holy grail of in-depth understanding of scientific concepts for our K-12 students. We have progressed in the realization that students can not meaningfully learn a long laundry list of terms, vocabulary, and factoids. We have recognized the sensibility of attempting to focus our educational efforts on fewer, unifying themes/concepts. However, we continue to fail at providing students with the most important organizing themes of all, the NOS and scientific inquiry. Despite volumes of research we continue to believe that students will come to understand scientific inquiry and the NOS simply by "doing science." Such an expectation is equivalent to assuming that individuals will come to understand the mechanism of breathing simply by breathing. Obviously, this is not the case. Doing science is certainly a start, but students need to reflect on what it is they are doing. They need to be engaged in discussions of why scientific investigations are designed in certain ways. Students need to discuss the assumptions inherent to any scientific investigation and the implications these assumptions have for the results. Furthermore, students need to discuss the fact that science is done by humans and the implications this has for the knowledge that is produced. These questions are but a few and you can certainly develop many more. My point, however, is quite simple. The NOS and scientific inquiry need to be addressed explicitly during science instruction. They need to be given status equal to that of traditional subject matter. Would we ever expect a student to implicitly learn pH? Without such explicit instructional attention, students will continue to learn subject matter without context and the visions of reform in science education will progress no further than they have in the past.
References
Abd-El-Khalick, F. (1998). The influence of history of science courses on students' conceptions of the nature of science. Unpublished Doctoral Dissertation, Oregon State University.
Aikenhead, G. (1973). The measurement of high school students' knowledge about science and scientists. Science Education, 57(4), 359-349.
Akindehin, F. (1988). Effect of an instructional package on preservice science teachers' understanding of the nature of science and acquisition of science-related attitudes. Science Education, 72(1), 73-82.
Alvarez, W., & Asaro, F. (1990, Oct.) An extraterrestrial impact. Scientific American, 78-84.
American Association for the Advancement of Science. (1990). Science for all Americans. New York: Oxford University Press.
American Association for the Advancement of Science. (1993). Benchmarks for science literacy: A Project 2061 report. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bady, R. A. (1979). Students' understanding of the logic of hypothesis testing. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 16(1), 61-65.
Billeh, V. Y., & Hasan, O. E. (1975). Factors influencing teachers' gain in understanding the nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 12(3), 209-219.
Broadhurst, N. A. (1970). A study of selected learning outcomes of graduating high school students in South Australian schools. Science Education, 54(1), 17-21.
Carey, R. L., & Stauss, N. G. (1968). An analysis of the understanding of the nature of science by prospective secondary science teachers. Science Education, 52(4), 358-363.
Carey, R. L., & Stauss, N. G. (1970). An analysis of experienced science teachers' understanding of the nature of science. School Science and Mathematics, 70(5), 366-376.
Central Association of Science and Mathematics Teachers (1907). A consideration of the principles that should determine the courses in biology in the secondary schools. School Science and Mathematics, 7, 241-247.
Chalmers, A. F. (1982). What is this thing called science? (2nd ed.). Queensland, Australia: University of Queensland Press. Courtillot, V. (1990, Oct.) A volcanic eruption. Scientific American, 85-92
Durkee, P. (1974). An analysis of the appropriateness and utilization of TOUS with special reference to high-ability students studying physics. Science Education, 58(3), 343-356.
Glen, W. (1990). What killed the dinosaurs? American Scientist, 78, 354-370
Haukoos, G. D., & Penick, J. E. (1985). The effects of classroom climate on college science students: A replication study. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 22(2), 163-168.
Hrdy, S. B. (1986). Empathy, polyandry, and the myth of the coy female. In R. Bleier (Ed.), Feminist approaches to science (pp. 119-146). Perganon Publishers.
Jones, K. M. (1969). The attainment of understandings about the scientific enterprise, scientists, and the aims and methods of science by students in a college physical science course. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 6(1), 47-49.
Kimball, M. E. (1967-68). Understanding the nature of science: A comparison of scientists and science teachers. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 5, 110-120.
Klopfer, L. E. (1969). The teaching of science and the history of science. Journal of Research for Science Teaching, 6, 87-95.
Klopfer, L. E., & Cooley, W. W. (1963). The history of science cases for high schools in the development of student understanding of science and scientists. Journal of Research for Science Teaching, 1(1), 33-47.
Klopfer, L. E., & Watson, F. G. (1957). Historical materials and high school science teaching. The Science Teacher, 24(6), 264-293.
Lavach, J. F. (1969). Organization and evaluation of an inservice program in the history of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 6, 166-170.
Lawson, A. E. (1982). The nature of advanced reasoning and science instruction. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 19, 743-760.
Lederman, N. G. (1992). Students' and teachers' conceptions of the nature of science: A review of the research. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 29(4), 331-359.
Lederman, N. G., & Abd-El-Khalick, F. (1998). Avoiding de-natured science: Activities that promote understandings of the nature of science. In W.
McComas (Ed.), The nature of science in science education: Rationales and strategies, pp.83-126. The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Lederman, N. G., & Niess, M. (1997). The nature of science: Naturally? School Science and Mathematics, 97(1), 1-2.
Lederman, N. G., & O'Malley, M. (1990). Students' perceptions of tentativeness in science: Development, use, and sources of change. Science Education, 74(2), 225-239.
Lovejoy, C. O. (1981). The origin of man. Science, 211, 341-350.
Luchessa, K., & Lederman, N. G. (1992). Real fossils, real science. The Science Teacher, 59, 68-92.
Mackay, L. D. (1971). Development of understanding about the nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 8(1), 57-66.
Mead, M., & Metraux, R. (1957). Image of the scientist among high school students. Science, 126, 384-390.
National Research Council (1996). National science education standards. Washington, DC: National Academic Press.
National Science Teachers Association. (1982). Science-technology-society: Science education for the 1980s. (An NSTA position statement). Washington, DC: Author.
Ogunniyi, M. B. (1983). Relative effects of a history/philosophy of science course on student teachers' performance on two models of science. Research in Science & Technological Education, 1(2), 193-199.
Olstad, R. G. (1969). The effect of science teaching methods on the understanding of science. Science Education, 53(1), 9-11.
Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge.
Popper, K. R. (1988). The open universe: An argument for indeterminism. London: Routledge.
Raup, D. (1991). Extinction: Bad genes or bad luck? New York: W W Norton & Co.
Riley, J. P., II (1979). The influence of hands-on science process training on preservice teachers' acquisition of process skills and attitude toward science and science teaching. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 16(5), 373-384.
Rowe, M. B. (1974). A humanistic intent: The program of preservice elementary education at the University of Florida. Science Education, 58, 369-376.
Rubba, P. A., & Andersen, H. (1978). Development of an instrument to assess secondary school students' understanding of the nature of scientific knowledge. Science Education, 62(4), 449-459.
Rutherford, F. J., Holton, G., & Watson, F. G. (1970). The project physics course. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Solomon, J., Duveen, J., Scot, L., & McCarthy, S. (1992). Teaching about the nature of science through history: Action research in the classroom. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 29(4), 409-421.
Spears, J., & Zollman, D. (1977). The influence of structured versus unstructured laboratory on students' understanding the process of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 14(1), 33-38.
Tamir, P., & Zohar, A. (1991). Anthropomorphism and teleology in reasoning about biological phenomena. Science Education, 75(1), 57-68.
Trent, J. (1965). The attainment of the concept "understanding science" using contrasting physics courses. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 3(3), 224-229.
Troxel, V. A. (1968). Analysis of instructional outcomes of students involved with three sources in high school chemistry. Washington, DC: US Department of Health, Education, and Welfare, Office of Education.
Welch, W. W., & Walberg, H. J. (1972). A national experiment in curriculum evaluation. American Educational Research Journal, 9(3), 373-383.
Wilson, L. (1954). A study of opinions related to the nature of science and its purpose in society. Science Education, 38(2), 236-242.
Yager, R. E., & Wick, J. W. (1966). Three emphases in teaching biology: A statistical comparison of results. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 4, 16-20.
To get to the top of this page, click here.
To get back to the current issue of the EJSE, click here.
To get back to the EJSE's Archive page, click here.